In his answer to the question “Distinction between typeclasses MonadPlus
, Alternative
, and Monoid
?”, Edward Kmett says that
Moreover, even if
Applicative
was a superclass ofMonad
, you’d wind up needing theMonadPlus
class anyways, because obeyingempty <*> m = empty
isn’t strictly enough to prove that
empty >>= f = empty
So claiming that something is a
MonadPlus
is stronger than claiming it isAlternative
.
It’s clear that any applicative functor which is not a monad is automatically an example of an Alternative
which is not a MonadPlus
, but Edward Kmett’s answer implies that there exists a monad which is an Alternative
but not a MonadPlus
: its empty
and <|>
would satisfy the Alternative
laws,1 but not the MonadPlus
laws.2 I can’t come up with an example of this by myself; does anybody know of one?
1 I wasn’t able to find a canonical reference for a set of Alternative
laws, but I lay out what I believe them to be roughly halfway through my answer to the question “Confused by the meaning of the Alternative
type class and its relationship to other type classes” (search for the phrase “right distributivity”). The four laws I believe ought to hold are:
<*>
): (f <|> g) <*> a = (f <*> a) <|> (g <*> a)
<*>
): empty <*> a = empty
fmap
): f <$> (a <|> b) = (f <$> a) <|> (f <$> b)
fmap
): f <$> empty = empty
I’d also happily accept being given a more useful set of Alternative
laws.
2 I know that there’s some ambiguity about what the MonadPlus
laws are; I’m happy with an answer that uses left distribution or left catch, although I would weakly prefer the former.
The clue to your answer is in the HaskellWiki about MonadPlus you linked to:
Which rules? Martin & Gibbons choose Monoid, Left Zero, and Left Distribution. This makes
[]
a MonadPlus, but notMaybe
orIO
.
So according to your favoured choice, Maybe
isn't a MonadPlus (although there's an instance, it doesn't satisfy left distribution). Let's prove it satisfies Alternative.
Maybe
is an Alternative<*>
): (f <|> g) <*> a = (f <*> a) <|> (g <*> a)
Case 1: f=Nothing
:
(Nothing <|> g) <*> a = (g) <*> a -- left identity <|>
= Nothing <|> (g <*> a) -- left identity <|>
= (Nothing <*> a) <|> (g <*> a) -- left failure <*>
Case 2: a=Nothing
:
(f <|> g) <*> Nothing = Nothing -- right failure <*>
= Nothing <|> Nothing -- left identity <|>
= (f <*> Nothing) <|> (g <*> Nothing) -- right failure <*>
Case 3: f=Just h, a = Just x
(Just h <|> g) <*> Just x = Just h <*> Just x -- left bias <|>
= Just (h x) -- success <*>
= Just (h x) <|> (g <*> Just x) -- left bias <|>
= (Just h <*> Just x) <|> (g <*> Just x) -- success <*>
<*>
): empty <*> a = empty
That's easy, because
Nothing <*> a = Nothing -- left failure <*>
fmap
): f <$> (a <|> b) = (f <$> a) <|> (f <$> b)
Case 1: a = Nothing
f <$> (Nothing <|> b) = f <$> b -- left identity <|>
= Nothing <|> (f <$> b) -- left identity <|>
= (f <$> Nothing) <|> (f <$> b) -- failure <$>
Case 2: a = Just x
f <$> (Just x <|> b) = f <$> Just x -- left bias <|>
= Just (f x) -- success <$>
= Just (f x) <|> (f <$> b) -- left bias <|>
= (f <$> Just x) <|> (f <$> b) -- success <$>
fmap
): f <$> empty = empty
Another easy one:
f <$> Nothing = Nothing -- failure <$>
Maybe
isn't a MonadPlusLet's prove the assertion that Maybe
isn't a MonadPlus: We need to show that mplus a b >>= k = mplus (a >>= k) (b >>= k)
doesn't always hold. The trick is, as ever, to use some binding to sneak very different values out:
a = Just False
b = Just True
k True = Just "Made it!"
k False = Nothing
Now
mplus (Just False) (Just True) >>= k = Just False >>= k
= k False
= Nothing
here I've used bind (>>=)
to snatch failure (Nothing
) from the jaws of victory because Just False
looked like success.
mplus (Just False >>= k) (Just True >>= k) = mplus (k False) (k True)
= mplus Nothing (Just "Made it!")
= Just "Made it!"
Here the failure (k False
) was calculated early, so got ignored and we "Made it!"
.
So, mplus a b >>= k = Nothing
but mplus (a >>= k) (b >>= k) = Just "Made it!"
.
You can look at this as me using >>=
to break the left-bias of mplus
for Maybe
.
Just in case you felt I hadn't done enough tedious deriving, I'll prove the identities I used:
Firstly
Nothing <|> c = c -- left identity <|>
Just d <|> c = Just d -- left bias <|>
which come from the instance declaration
instance Alternative Maybe where
empty = Nothing
Nothing <|> r = r
l <|> _ = l
Secondly
f <$> Nothing = Nothing -- failure <$>
f <$> Just x = Just (f x) -- success <$>
which just come from (<$>) = fmap
and
instance Functor Maybe where
fmap _ Nothing = Nothing
fmap f (Just a) = Just (f a)
Thirdly, the other three take a bit more work:
Nothing <*> c = Nothing -- left failure <*>
c <*> Nothing = Nothing -- right failure <*>
Just f <*> Just x = Just (f x) -- success <*>
Which comes from the definitions
instance Applicative Maybe where
pure = return
(<*>) = ap
ap :: (Monad m) => m (a -> b) -> m a -> m b
ap = liftM2 id
liftM2 :: (Monad m) => (a1 -> a2 -> r) -> m a1 -> m a2 -> m r
liftM2 f m1 m2 = do { x1 <- m1; x2 <- m2; return (f x1 x2) }
instance Monad Maybe where
(Just x) >>= k = k x
Nothing >>= _ = Nothing
return = Just
so
mf <*> mx = ap mf mx
= liftM2 id mf mx
= do { f <- mf; x <- mx; return (id f x) }
= do { f <- mf; x <- mx; return (f x) }
= do { f <- mf; x <- mx; Just (f x) }
= mf >>= \f ->
mx >>= \x ->
Just (f x)
so if mf
or mx
are Nothing, the result is also Nothing
, whereas if mf = Just f
and mx = Just x
, the result is Just (f x)