The third chapter of CPDT briefly discusses why negative inductive types are forbidden in Coq. If we had
Inductive term : Set :=
| App : term -> term -> term
| Abs : (term -> term) -> term.
then we could easily define a function
Definition uhoh (t : term) : term :=
match t with
| Abs f => f t
| _ => t
end.
so that the term uhoh (Abs uhoh)
would be non-terminating, with which "we would be able to prove every theorem".
I understand the non-termination part, but I don't get how we can prove anything with it. How would one prove False
using term
as defined above?
Reading your question made me realize that I didn't quite understand Adam's argument either. But inconsistency in this case results quite easily from Cantor's usual diagonal argument (a never-ending source of paradoxes and puzzles in logic). Consider the following assumptions:
Section Diag.
Variable T : Type.
Variable test : T -> bool.
Variables x y : T.
Hypothesis xT : test x = true.
Hypothesis yF : test y = false.
Variable g : (T -> T) -> T.
Variable g_inv : T -> (T -> T).
Hypothesis gK : forall f, g_inv (g f) = f.
Definition kaboom (t : T) : T :=
if test (g_inv t t) then y else x.
Lemma kaboom1 : forall t, kaboom t <> g_inv t t.
Proof.
intros t H.
unfold kaboom in H.
destruct (test (g_inv t t)) eqn:E; congruence.
Qed.
Lemma kaboom2 : False.
Proof.
assert (H := @kaboom1 (g kaboom)).
rewrite -> gK in H.
congruence.
Qed.
End Diag.
This is a generic development that could be instantiated with the term
type defined in CPDT: T
would be term
, x
and y
would be two elements of term
that we can test discriminate between (e.g. App (Abs id) (Abs id)
and Abs id
). The key point is the last assumption: we assume that we have an invertible function g : (T -> T) -> T
which, in your example, would be Abs
. Using that function, we play the usual diagonalization trick: we define a function kaboom
that is by construction different from every function T -> T
, including itself. The contradiction results from that.